Constructing Justice: Fairness, Inclusiveness and Understanding

AuthorJohn East
PositionBA (Hons) (Philosophy and Political Science); MA (Political Science); JD (Candidate), Bora Laskin Faculty of Law, Thunder Bay, Ontario, Canada. The author would like to thank Professors Drake and Maundrell for their invaluable input as supervisors of this article. He would also like to thank Ms Amanda Somek for her contributions as editor. Ms ...
Pages1-26
[2017] 16 COLR 1
1"
CONSTRUCTING JUSTICE: FAIRNESS, INCLUSIVENESS, AND
UNDERSTANDING
John East*
A INTRODUCTION
In Political Liberalism, Rawls presents a theory of justice endeavoring to account for the fact
that in a modern democratic society, citizens hold irreconcilable religious and philosophical
conceptions of the world. He does not reconcile these competing views within a theory of justice,
rather he conceptualises justice as a purely political matter. In essence, Rawls privatises how
citizens should connect their underlying personal values to an overarching principle of justice in
a reasonable and rational way. His approach is constructivist in nature and attempts to be as
inclusive as possible. Principles of justice are built from the ground up and depend on
abstractions from specific features of the social world, starting with the basic principle of the
social contract.1 We do not enter democratic society voluntarily, but we are born into it. We find
ourselves situated in a political society at a particular moment in time. Given that our presence in
this society is not an association, a theory of justice should speak to the extent that democratic
citizens are free. Principles of justice should specify fair terms of social co-operation and
regulate the division of benefits that arise, along with the encumbrances required to sustain those
benefits.2
Ultimately, Rawls hopes the most marginalised groups of society will find motivation to adopt
justice as fairness. Yet basing principles of justice on abstractions of a uniquely liberal social
world raises the question: despite Rawls’ constructive efforts, how inclusive and motivating can
his justice really be? One way to test the validity of this approach is to take fundamental ideas
central to his conception, and theorise about exclusionary effects they may have on groups
situated at the far fringes of society. The Anishinabe or Anishinabek are an aboriginal group of
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
*BA (Hons) (Philosophy and Political Science); MA (Political Science); JD (Candidate), Bora Laskin Faculty of
Law, Thunder Bay, Ontario, Canada. The author would like to thank Professors Drake and Maundrell for their
invaluable input as supervisors of this article. He would also like to tha nk Ms Amanda Somek for her contributions
as editor. Ms Somek's advice and input played a crucial role in preparing this article for publishing.
1 John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Harvard University Press 2001) 3-17.
2 ibid.
[2017] 16 COLR 2
2"
peoples fitting this description. More importantly, some Anishinabe communities oppose basic
assumptions of the liberal doctrine, particularly when it comes to how they conceive of property
or land. They teach that we cannot and should not privately own land.
Working through this thought experiment to its final conclusions reveals that basing justice on
liberal assumptions has similar exclusionary effects as theories of justice that purport to
illuminate some universal morality or truth. We must slightly reconfigure Rawls’ political
conception if citizens who hold stark and contradictory views are to adopt justice as fairness.
Overall, justice as fairness becomes more stable and inclusive if we couch it in a specific version
of the pragmatic theory of truth, championed by the pragmatist Richard Rorty.
This article is divided into three key sections. The first section explains key concepts that are
crucial to understanding justice as fairness and include the reasonable comprehensive doctrine,
original position, and overlapping consensus. Special focus is given to how some of these
principles are dependent on uniquely liberal ideals. The second section begins by highlighting
critiques of Rawls’ argument concerning citizens’ motivation to form an overlapping consensus
of justice. The ontological differences between some Anishinabe views of property and
underlying liberal assumptions are so stark it results in a motivational deficit. The last section
explains that to account for this deficit we should ground Rawls’ constructivist approach in a
pragmatic theory of truth.
B KEY CONCEPTS
I Reasonable Comprehensive Doctrine
Rawls argues that each citizen will be able to connect their reasonable comprehensive doctrine to
an overarching conception of justice in a reasonable and rational way. Understanding his
argument requires an explanation of what a reasonable comprehensive doctrine is. We derive the
concept of reasonable from the assumption that society is a system of fair co-operation. Persons
are fundamentally reasonable when they are ready to propose principles and standards of fair
terms of social co-operation.3 People willingly abide by the standards if they feel assured that
others will too. Reasonable people are not motivated by personal desires for good per se; rather,
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
3 John Rawls, Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press 1993) 50-52.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT