The Fallacy of the Cyberspace Fallacy: A Re-Examination of Cyberlibertarianism

Date01 January 2018
Author
25
e Fallacy of the Cyberspace Fallacy:
A Re-Examination of Cyberlibertarianism
BARRY O’FIACHÁIN*
Introduction
Fundamental to the operation of law is the certainty of knowing when it does and
does not apply. As a general rule, where the geographical location of an individual
or object at a particular time is determinable, the appropriate legal jurisdiction
and corresponding legal regime can be easily inferred.1 However, when applied to
cyberspace, this seemingly straightforward principle becomes more complicated.
Early conceptions of cyberspace were of a utopia where individuals could escape
their physical boundaries like never before.2 is cyberlibertarian idea asserted
that within the virtual world, eective regulation by real world states could not be
achieved. Over time however, this way of thinking has withered away. Since the
introduction of Chris Reed’s ‘cyberspace fallacy’ argument, there has been a general
consensus that cyberlibertarianism has been undermined and discredited.
In the time since the introduction of the ‘cyberspace fallacy’ argument it has become
clear that the structure of the internet and its regulation are not as simple as those
who rejected cyberlibertarianism once suggested. Our perceptions of the internet
have changed. While we traditionally saw the act of visiting a website as involving a
request sent to a remote server, which subsequently returns text and images, we now
consider it akin to travelling to a legitimate place.3 e cyberlibertarians appear to
have appreciated this dierence before anyone, but, at the time, the internet was
too young for us to fully understand the impact one’s choice of perspective can
have. is is no longer the case.
In addition to the debate over perspective, jurisdictional complications persist in
the attempt to introduce an eective regulatory system capable of transcending
borders. Such problems have been exacerbated by the development of technology
itself. An ever changing and advancing phenomenon, this development is clearly
something the law has struggled to keep pace with. All of this development and
legal diculty appears to lend renewed credibility to cyberlibertarianism and
* B.C.L. (Politics) (UCD), LL.M. (LSE), Trainee Solicitor at A&L Goodbody.
1 Chris Reed, Internet Law: Text and Materials (2nd edn, Cambridge University Press 2004) 217.
2 Mary Anne Franks, ‘Unwilling Avatars: Idealism and Discrimination in Cyberspace’ (2011) 20
Columbia Journal of Gender and Law 225.
3 Orin S. Kerr, ‘e Problem of Perspective in Internet Law’ (2003) 91 e Georgetown Law Journal
386.
26  ’
forces us to question whether the cyberspace fallacy argument properly addresses
its claims. Until now, the answer has been overwhelmingly yes, but it may be time
to re-examine cyberlibertarianism from the internal perspective, rather than the
traditional external perspective. It may be that the only fallacy to be found is in the
arguments that dismissed the cyberlibertarian ideas as fallacy.
e aim of this paper is to carry out that re-examination of the cyberlibertarian
position from an internal perspective, while having regard to network
communitarianism, in order to test the strength of Chris Reed’s cyberspace fallacy.
A selection of seminal case law in this area will be analysed, before considering
whether cyberlaw is capable of overcoming its jurisdictional and technological
obstacles and eectively regulating the internet.
Cyberlibertarianism and e Cyberspace Fallacy
Cyberlibertarianism describes an ideology that views the internet and the
development of associated technologies as decentralised and liberating modes of
communication that operate outside the remit of centralised governments. Due to
the connement of laws to the jurisdiction in which they operate and the ability
of online content to ow without regard to geographical or political borders,4
cyberlibertarians believe that the internet is a borderless environment, incapable
of legitimate and eective regulation by traditional law-makers.5 is borderless
environment allows those in cyberspace to engage in regulatory arbitrage, whereby
they take advantage of the choice between regulators to achieve a regulatory
settlement which will not impact on their activities.6
In this vein, Johnson and Post argued that cyberspace should be recognised as a
separate legal jurisdiction from the real world, without recourse to national courts
and laws.7 Such a jurisdiction would be capable of self-regulation by online users
and service providers and would transcend the boundaries of national sovereignty.8
Similarly, John Perry Barlow declared that the internet cannot be subject to any
existing law making authority and that the governments of the world have no
sovereignty over it.9 is statement was in response to the introduction by United
States legislators of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, through which, Barlow
4 Reed (n 1) 217.
5 Andrew Murray, Information Technology Law: e Law and Society (2nd edn, Oxford University
Press 2013), 55.
6 ibid 58.
7 Lorna E. Gillies, ‘Addressing the “Cyberspace Fallacy”: Targeting the Jurisdiction of an Electronic
Consumer Contract’ (2008) 16 International Journal of Law and Information Technology 244.
8 David R . Johnson and David Post, ‘Law and Borders: e Rise of Law in Cyberspace’ (1996) 48
Stanford Law Review 1388.
9 Andrew Murray, ‘Uses and Abuses of Cyberspace: Coming to Grips with the Present Dangers’ in
Antonio Cassese (ed), Realising Utopia: e Future of International Law (Oxford University Press
2012) 500.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT