The Provocation Predicament

Date01 January 2010
AuthorAnthony Mcgrath
The Provocation Predicament
Dr AN THON Y MCG R AT H
Provocation is a difficult and contentious aspect of the law of criminal
homicide, perhaps best understood amongst its historical context before the
complexities of conflicting dicta, precedence, practice, and academic
comment blurred its boundaries and scope. One of the primary prerequisites
of the criminal law has always been that individuals control their behaviour;
indeed this is the standard upon which the viability of any society depends,
and the importance the criminal law attaches to the maintaining of self-
control reflects the innate connection between the elementary principles of
criminal liability and the moral infrastructure of our society.
The presence of provocation in our common law serves to operate as a
partial defence to murder.1As it does not function as a complete defence
exonerating the offender, an acquittal will never be justified. This mitigation
acknowledges that some act or series of acts done or said, or a combination
of both, emanating from a person who does not necessarily have to be the
victim, can provoke the offender to lose control and commit a fatal act. This
loss of self-control is deemed to be temporary insofar as the offender would
be able to avail of the defence of insanity if the loss were in any way
permanent. More significantly, there is also a recognition that the loss of
control is not entirely complete; that there remained a possibility that the
offender could, but did not, reason himself out of his emotion.
Academics have long debated whether provocation amounts to a partial
defence because the killer claims to have done the right thing: a justification;
or that what he has done is wrong but that the provocation amounts to an
extenuating circumstance: an excuse. The doctrine of provocation emerged
in parallel with the development of early quixotic concepts of honour, where
it was expected that an insult or attack upon the esteem of a man be
avenged with resort to a lethal weapon. It therefore initially developed on
a justificatory basis, for the cause of the killing “rested not in the hatred or
design of the slayer but rather in the actions of the deceased who aroused
the slayer’s passions.”2This explains the early requirements that the
provocative conduct had to be unlawful, thus making the response of killing
less socially adverse, and that it had to emanate from the deceased, so that
1In most common law j urisdictions, provocation can only be invoked to a charge of
murder but is considered a mitigating circumstance when sentencing for most other
criminal offences.
2Ashworth, “The Doctrine of Provocation” (1976) 35 Cambridge Law Journal 292,
p 293.
1&2 HJ2010:Layout 1 27/05/2010 17:02 Page 26

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT